Archive for the ‘Democracy’ Category

Mayday! Mayday! Mayday! Democracy needs you and so does FFRF! – Freedom From Religion Foundation

Mayday! Mayday! Secular democracy is capsizing!

The Freedom From Religion Foundation is gravely concerned about the state of state/church separation and individual freedoms in the United States.

As this is written, were readying a lawsuit against the expected passage of a law requiring large Ten Commandments posters to be placed in every Texas classroom. Were ready to sue if the Catholic Archdiocese of Oklahoma City succeeds in being approved to establish the nations first publicly funded sectarian charter school. Were also eyeing a possible challenge over a Texas bill to place a monument to the unborn on statehouse grounds that is a replica of a devotional statue of an enrobed Virgin Mary incubating a fetal Jesus.

Were seeing religiously inspired state legislative battles over abortion rights, LGBTQ rights, book bans and more.

The good news is the growth and influence of the Nones (religiously unaffiliated, including FFRF members) and our ability to counter the religious zealots. Please see the attached FFRF Spring/Summer 2023 appeal with more about your vital role as a None and how our secular movement can rescue our democracy.

If you've already donated recently, thank you so much consider this for your information.

Forward!

Co-PresidentsFreedom From Religion Foundation

P.S. Donate directly at ffrf.us/donate.

Read more from the original source:
Mayday! Mayday! Mayday! Democracy needs you and so does FFRF! - Freedom From Religion Foundation

The Jerusalem rally was a reminder that democracy didn’t lose; the … – JNS.org

(April 30, 2023 / JNS) Those of us who were among the hundreds of thousands of participants in the right-wing rally in Jerusalem on Thursday evening werent surprised when the resistance bloc pulled a two-fer: downplaying the significance of and attendance at the event, on the one hand; and treating the happening as evidence that Israeli democracy is in danger of annihilation at the hands of fanatics, on the other.

Nor did we imagine that coverage from most media outlets would be accurate, let alone fair, since theyve been acting all along like a branch of the protest movement. Instead, we drew encouragement from the throngs of fellow members of the national camp who turned up to bolster the government and urge it not to be bullied into backtracking on its mandate.

Both were necessary under the circumstances, with the Orwellian doublespeak of the opposition having become so blatant that its putting regular propaganda to shame. Indeed, the projection on the part of the protest instigators isnt merely jaw-dropping (calling the government, rather than those trying to topple it, a coup, for instance); its actually been successful at sowing self-doubt in coalition circles.

Ahead of the opening of the Knessets summer session on Sunday, then, it was particularly crucial for lawmakers to be reminded of the populace that isnt drinking the Kool-Aidthose still expecting and demanding judicial reform, with or without a broad consensus. It was also important to highlight that compromise on this or any other issue isnt on the agenda of the forces spearheading the weekly demonstrations.

The points were made amid much good cheer and lots of applause for the speakers. Justice Minister Yariv Levin was given an especially warm welcome, in addition to cautionary chants of Dont be afraid!

Subscribe to The JNS Daily Syndicateby email and never missour top stories

The message was that he shouldnt cave on the judicial-reform process that the government had put on hold. This was done to allow for negotiations to bring about an agreement and prevent civil war.

Levins speech was aimed at reassuring his base that he hadnt abandoned the mission, and assuaging the fears of opponents.

We are told that the reform is intended to take over the Supreme Court, but the truth is the opposite, he said. We want a court for everyone: liberals, conservatives, right and left. Everyone.

He went on: They say that the reform is intended to impose the lifestyle of one public on another. The truth, of course, is the opposite. There is nothing in the reform that involves coercion or an infringement on the individual rights that are important to all of us. We are told that if the reform passes, there will be a dictatorship. There is no bigger lie than that.

He also addressed Labor Party leader Merav Michaeli and the many feminists whove been wearing costumes from the Netflix series, The Handmaids Tale, based on the dystopian novel by Margaret Atwood.

Join us so that we have a court that punishes rapists and doesnt seek ways to make it easier for them; a court that cares for an elderly woman in south Tel Aviv and not for infiltrators who harm her; a court that protects the lives of IDF soldiers not terrorists.

All well and good. But his words were far less noteworthy than the reaction they elicited from protest leader Moshe Bogie Yaalon. The former defense minister, who used to be politically and ideologically aligned with Levin, is now a key promoter of the above-mentioned slurs.

The fact that he who bears the title of justice minister has not yet been fired and arrested, after the mendacious incitement speech that spilled the blood of Israeli judges, is a normalization of the insanity, Yaalon tweeted on Friday. The fact that at the head of the Israeli government, which is trying to carry out a coup dtat, is under indictment for serious crimes and prohibited from dealing with the judiciary due to a clear conflict of interest, is a normalization of the insanity; the fact that the heads of the opposition are conducting negotiations under the auspices of the president of the country on the coup dtat proposal (the Levin-[Simcha] Rothman legislation) is a normalization of the insanity squared.

So, in Yaalons view, Levin deserves to be sacked and hauled off to jail. Talk about lunacy.

As if any of these statements werent sufficient to warrant a psychological examination for their author, he proceeded to demand of the representatives engaged in talks at the Presidents Residence that they get out of there and let the criminal government, which has caused and is causing unprecedented damage to the country and its citizens, deal with [its own mess] so that its days will be numbered.

His next cynical feat was to invoke and appropriate Zeev Jabotinskythe father of Revisionist Zionism, precursor of the Likud Party heading the current governmentby using the title of the latters famous 1923 essay.

Join the Iron Wall of the mighty protest, which will not allow a dictatorship! Democracy will win, he wrote, before going on in his lengthy thread to describe the scenes from Thursdays extremist messianic incitement demonstration as shocking, and accusing Levin of inciting blood-curdling libels against Israeli judges, as if they support rapists and terrorists!

Never mind that Yaalon is fully cognizant of the specific cases in question, each of which actually did favor the perpetrators. On a roll, he told his friends in the opposition that they are the messengers of the vast majority that supports democracy and independent judges. The inciters wont get their way. Israel will not become a messianic dictatorship with an inciting regime. The huge democratic majoritythe democratic iron wallwill defeat this craziness! Democracy will win.

What he and his ilk have been trying to obfuscate, however, is that democracy never lost; the left did, at the ballot box in November. The 600,000 Israelis who arrived in the capital on Thursday from around the country were simply reasserting this reality. Let the government not forget it.

Ruthie Blum is a Tel Aviv-based columnist and commentator. She writes and lectures on Israeli politics and culture, as well as on U.S.-Israel relations. The winner of the Louis Rappaport award for excellence in commentary, she is the author of the book To Hell in a Handbasket: Carter, Obama, and the Arab Spring.

Continued here:
The Jerusalem rally was a reminder that democracy didn't lose; the ... - JNS.org

John Ivison: Interference news has Liberals looking soft on a country intent on undermining our democracy – National Post

OTTAWA The serenity shown by one senior Liberal official in late March over the Chinese foreign interference saga was at odds with the fever that was gripping Ottawa.

This advertisement has not loaded yet, but your article continues below.

We apologize, but this video has failed to load.

At the time, it seemed the government was in real trouble. There was compelling testimony that suggested the Liberal party was warned by the security services that some of its candidates were helped by the Chinese government in successive elections.

Yet, as it was explained to me by the senior Liberal, the issue was considered overblown; the process of appointing a special rapporteur to look into allegations Beijing had sought to ensure a Liberal government would take time to come to a conclusion; and, that, absent new revelations, the story would die down.

The plan was cynical but proven. The problem with it is that the Globe and Mails security agency sources appear intent on ensuring there are new revelations.

This advertisement has not loaded yet, but your article continues below.

Mondays paper included details of a 2021 intelligence assessment that said China is using incentives and punishments as part of an influence network that included interrogating relatives of a Canadian MP. Sources told the Globe that the MP is Conservative Michael Chong and that the diplomat in Canada handling the file, Zhao Wei, is still accredited to work in this country.

Chong said in a statement Monday he is disappointed that he was not told his family in Hong Kong had been identified. The government did not inform me that a diplomat was targeting my family, nor did the government take any action to expel the diplomat responsible for orchestrating this intimidation campaign.

This advertisement has not loaded yet, but your article continues below.

He said he has been briefed by the Canadian Security Intelligence Service but was not told about the risk of sanction against his family. My conclusion is that the PMO did not authorize CSIS to inform me of this specific threat. The fact that the government neither informed me, nor took any action is indicative of its ongoing laissez-faire attitude toward the PRCs (Peoples Republic of China) intimidation tactics.

During question period, Conservative Leader Pierre Poilievre pointed out that the Chinese consider Canada uniquely vulnerable to foreign influence efforts because there are no protections such as the foreign influence registry that exist in countries like the U.S. and Australia.

Poilievre said that Trudeau knew about the threats for two years and did exactly nothing.

This advertisement has not loaded yet, but your article continues below.

Will the prime minister finally stand up for this country and its people against a foreign dictatorship that has been interfering in our land for far too long?

The prime minister engaged in a lengthy damage limitation exercise, saying he has asked officials to follow up on the Globe report. It is absolutely unacceptable to see anyone being intimidated, especially a member of Parliament in this House, he said.

But he rebuffed calls for a full public inquiry by pointing to the special rapporteur process.

Former governor general David Johnston has been asked to look into foreign influence allegations, with a mandate to recommend any additional mechanisms such as a public inquiry by May 23, and to release his first conclusions by the end of October.

This advertisement has not loaded yet, but your article continues below.

Even if you believe, as I do, that Johnston will not be cowed by fear or favour, such an extended timeline inevitably reduces the threat to a government that can use the process like a shield to stonewall the opposition.

The intensity has passed, the media have moved on and too many voters were confused about the details to get too angry.

But stories such as the targeting of Chongs family, the existence of Chinese police stations in Canada and the donation to the Trudeau Foundation orchestrated by Beijing and leading to the entire board resigning keep the issue of foreign interference bubbling away. The three stories dominated question period in the House of Commons on Monday.

Doubts about the Liberal partys role in all of this linger in the publics mind. Polls suggest voters are skeptical, not only of the Trudeau governments relationship with China, but also about the prime ministers ability to tell voters the truth about any given issue.

The continuing drip of news that presents the government as soft on a country intent on undermining our democracy will lead more people to reach the same conclusion as certain members of the security services that the Liberals were co-conspirators with Beijing, as one source put it to me.

Judgment may have been delayed, but it has not yet been denied.

The rest is here:
John Ivison: Interference news has Liberals looking soft on a country intent on undermining our democracy - National Post

Is Israel a democracy? Heres what Americans think – Brookings Institution

The unprecedented and sustained Israeli protests against the government of Prime Minister Benjamin Netanyahus proposed judicial overhaul that threatened to substantially weaken the judiciary have captured news headlines worldwide. They have also coincided with a spike in violence in the occupied Palestinian territories. Although the protests have largely ignored Israels military rule over millions of Palestinians, they drew attention to threats to democracy even within Israels pre-1967 borders. It is hard to know if these protests have had any impact on the way Americans perceive Israel, and if they did, in what direction. While these protests may have drawn attention to the right-wing governments autocratic ambitions, they may have also highlighted the existence of a free environment, at least for hundreds of thousands of Israeli citizens, to protest freely and reject the governments plans. Do Americans see Israel as a vibrant democracy or as something far less?

To find out, we fielded a few questions in our University of Maryland Critical Issues Poll with Ipsos, which I direct with my colleague Stella Rouse. The poll was conducted March 27-April 5, 2023, among 1,203 respondents by Ipsos probabilistic KnowledgePanel (margin of error 3.2%).

We asked: You may have been following recent developments in Israel, the West Bank, and Gaza. In your opinion which of the following is closer to describing the way Israel looks to you. We provided the following four options: a vibrant democracy; a flawed democracy; a state with restricted minority rights; a state with segregation similar to apartheid. The results were surprising on many levels.

First, the number of respondents who said they didnt know was very high for this kind of question: more than half of respondents overall and nearly two-thirds of Republicans. This number of people saying they didnt know is usually reserved for questions about which one would expect a lack of familiarity (questions about the Boycott, Divest, and Sanctions movement (BDS), for example). Typically, on matters of opinion, respondents often answer even when they dont fully know the issue. All this suggests that there is a level of discomfort among respondents in answering this question. This is also born out in the fact that the percentage of those who said they didnt know was very high even among those with a college education and above; among Republicans, most of those with college degrees and higher said: I dont know.

Second, in this case, one may expect far more public exposure to the issue. Israel has been an important topic in the American discourse for decades, especially among Republicans in recent years. It is typical to hear Israel referred to as the only democracy in the Middle East or with reference to its shared values with the United States. Yet, even among all those who responded, the highest percentage, 31%, was equally shared by those who described Israel as a flawed democracy and those who described it as a state with segregation similar to apartheid. Among Republicans, a 41% plurality said it is a vibrant democracy while 20% said it is a state with segregation similar to apartheid.

Among Democrats, the story was strikingly different: A plurality of those expressing an opinion, 44%, said it is a state with segregation similar to apartheid, followed by 34% who said its a flawed democracy. This is remarkable because the use of the term apartheid, in the American mainstream discourse, while increasingly heard, is still highly uncommon and even taboo in many circles.

Do these results reflect the impact of recent events in Israel/Palestine and the rise of the far-right government in Israel? It is difficult to tell, as this is the first time that we have asked this question in our polling.

It is notable, however, that in one of our tracking questions about U.S. policy toward Israel/Palestine, we found little change in attitudes from our October poll. In probing whether respondents want the United States to lean toward Israel, toward the Palestinians, or toward neither side, we found only a small decrease in the number who want the United States to lean toward Israel, mostly within the margin of error.

Finally, we asked respondents about their view of the BDS movement. In this case, we added the choice unfamiliar in addition to the choice dont know to try to further understand the meaning of the responses. Not surprisingly, a large number, 39%, said they were unfamiliar, while 26% said they dont know which is still a high percentage, possibly indicating they had some discomfort expressing an opinion on this issue as well.

When examining the results among those who offered an opinion, there was an unsurprisingly large difference between Democrats and Republicans. Among Republicans, 65% said they opposed BDS. Among Democrats, the picture was different: a plurality of those who expressed an opinion, 41%, said they supported it, while only 20% said they opposed it.

It is clear that public attitudes about Israel are shifting. The term apartheid appears to have become a common term among many Americans, especially Democrats, and even the BDS movement, which has faced considerable obstacles in the American mainstream, seems to have sizable support among Democrats who expressed their opinion. A recent Gallup poll found that, for the first time in their years of polling on Israeli-Palestinian issues, more Democrats sympathize with the Palestinians than with Israelis by a margin of 11 percentage points. And while about half of Republicans continue to say they want the United States to lean toward Israel, that support is diminishing among young Republicans 32% in the current poll and, as other research has shown, support for Israel is declining even among young evangelical Christians.

See the original post here:
Is Israel a democracy? Heres what Americans think - Brookings Institution

Plato’s Philosophy Is an Aristocratic Attack on Democracy and … – Jacobin magazine

Modern commentators trace the emergence of Western philosophy back to Plato. Karl Popper once suggested that Western thought has been Platonic or anti-Platonic but rarely ever non-Platonic, while Alfred North Whitehead famously quipped that the history of Western philosophy has been little more than footnotes to Plato.

One reason for his enduring influence is the sheer breadth of Platos writing. Across three dozen dialogues, Plato tackles everything from theology, metaphysics, and epistemology to political theory, the nature of love, and the theory of language. Another reason is the undeniable depth of Platos thought, which assimilates insights from his predecessors Parmenides and Pythagoras in particular while breaking new ground in many of the areas highlighted above.

A third reason, far less remarked upon, is the historical role that Platos philosophy has played in attacking democracy. His most influential work, The Republic, is a highly sophisticated argument against the democratic approach to government that had taken shape in Platos time. Platos uncompromising defense of human inequality has appealed to conservatives ever since.

By the time Plato was writing in the early decades of the fourth century BCE, Athens had been a democracy for more than a century. Starting with Solons reforms in the early sixth century BCE and continuing with the Cleisthenian reforms in 507, thousands of Athenian males won citizenship rights in the teeth of opposition from conservative aristocrats members of the Eupatridae who objected to this upending of the natural order of things.

Plato was a member of the Eupatridae on both sides of his family. His father was descended from the old kings of Athens, while his mothers family was even more prestigious, tracing its roots to the great Athenian lawgiver Solon. Members of Platos family were also heavily involved in contemporary politics. When he was in his early twenties, Platos uncle and his mothers cousin led a coup against Athenian democracy in the aftermath of defeat in the Peloponnesian War.

Writing about these events fifty years later, Plato recounts how he initially supported this antidemocratic coup in the hope that its leaders would set the city back onto the path of justice. Instead, they acted with brutality, slaughtering their opponents and tearing up the rule of law.

Plato wants his readers to know that he abhorred the behavior of his friends and relatives, but it is worth remembering that his letter was written long after the failure of the coup was a well-established fact. We cannot know what role Plato might have played had the coup been successful, particularly as he went on to have intimate relations with more successful tyrants in the region.

In this context, it is worth nothing that the letter outlining Platos opposition to his associates in Athens was actually written to exonerate his own record in the politics of Syracuse, where one of his long-standing supporters played a central role in turning a once-vibrant democracy into a bloodbath of civil war and internecine violence.

Members of Platos Academy were also directly involved in the Syracuse bloodletting. Platos Letter to the Friends of Dion was essentially written to eulogize his protg, despite Dions role in the cycle of violence, to denounce Dions rivals as men whom Plato had tried (and failed) to turn into philosopher-kings, and to exonerate Plato himself, in view of the disaster that was unfolding for ordinary people.

In spite of the killing and chaos that ensued, Plato never gave up his conviction that ordinary men and women were incapable of ruling themselves. He also retained his conviction that the easiest way to bring justice to the city-state would involve converting autocrats into philosopher-kings and that the nature of such justice could only be truly discerned from Platos own idealist philosophy.

Western philosophy was a product of the polis, a new form of political organization that arose in Greece during the period from 800 to 500 BCE. These city-states grew out of a Dark Age centered on warrior bands and rural villages. The value system that underpinned the older society was based on military achievement. Men followed leaders who could protect the family unit (oikos) and display excellence in battle.

In the period between 1100 and 800 BCE, warrior chieftains coalesced into a military aristocracy who controlled the land and differentiated themselves through noble lineage. As before, it was military virtue that commanded respect, as aristocrats secured honor through success in warfare and victory against rival noblemen. These values were encapsulated in the ideal of aret the strength and skill of a noble warrior coupled with his superiority over commoners.

The most important catalyst for the emerging polis was a population explosion facilitated by improvements in agriculture associated with the shift from bronze to iron. According to one estimate, the population increased by a factor of seven between 780 BCE and 720 BCE, creating a struggle for land that in turn resulted in a series of important consequences for the development of the polis.

An urban civilization slowly developed, helping to create the legal and spatial centers for these new communities. At the same time, there was a wave of outward migration, with Greeks founding hundreds of new colonies and re-establishing trade with older empires to their east and south. The struggle for land also brought the masses more fully into politics as they began to claim political representation, land redistribution, and debt forgiveness.

The latter point indicates the growing importance of a monetary economy, which further destabilized an aristocracy who needed wealth to maintain their power without wanting to lower themselves to commercial activity. Over time, the rise in commerce created differentials within the aristocracy as some families adopted to the new economic reality while others failed to do so. It also created a class of prosperous farmers who demanded political representation as their economic fortunes improved.

The development of hoplite warfare in the middle of the seventh century was another important milestone in the move toward citizen-states, as warfare was no longer the preserve of the aristocracy. Instead of noble warriors fighting on horseback, warfare was carried out by around a third of the adult male population who had the resources to afford the equipment of a hoplite infantryman.

The fact that political rights had historically been associated with participation in battle meant that it was very likely that power now would begin to open up, particularly as internal competition within the nobility meant that they never imposed a class state over the commoners. In this respect, the collapse of the Mycenaean Empire during the twelfth century BCE allowed essential space for the development of more democratic forms of decision-making centuries later.

One consequence of struggle among the elites was the rise of tyrants. These were aristocrats who emerged in a period of conflict to grab power for themselves. From 650 to 500 BCE, strongmen emerged in various poleis with the aim of breaking the political, familial, and religious bases of their aristocratic rivals.

The best way to achieve this was to elevate the importance of the polis as a civic and religious center. Tyrants were associated with investment in civic and religious infrastructure that fostered a sense of citizen-solidarity. They also offered small commercial loans to break the economic power of the aristocracy and enacted legal codes that replaced the informal judgements of the nobility with more formal laws erected by the polis itself.

Meanwhile, the gradual rise in commercial logic was dissolving traditional relationships while also increasing economic inequality. In Athens, the resulting struggles became particularly sharp around 594 BCE, as the development of a rising class of prosperous farmers was mirrored by a growing mass of poorer peasants. Renowned as a lawmaker, Solon was tasked with restoring civic harmony among the contending parties: the nobility, the yeoman farmers, and the poorer peasants.

To help the poorest farmers, he abolished the quasi-feudal hektmoroi system along with the debt slavery that resulted from it. He also opened political office to men of wealth and made the aristocracy more accountable to justice administered through the polis. His aim was to ensure a hierarchical form of social order (eunomia) based on the proportionate contributions made by different classes to the good of the state.

However, within half a century, the reforms of Solon had given way to an Athenian tyranny under Pisistratus. In the same mode as tyrants elsewhere, Pisistratus fostered a sense of Athenian citizenship while further weakening the power of the Eupatridae. In the subsequent battle to overthrow Hippias, the son of Pisistratus, Cleisthenes sought a base among the masses against the conservative wing of the aristocracy, led by Isagoras.

The victory of Cleisthenes was also a victory for the lower orders. To confirm it, Cleisthenes further weakened the traditional nobility by abolishing their kinship groups, known as phratry. The newer kinship groups were tied directly to the polis, making sure the Athenian citizenry would become a self-conscious and a self-defined political body.

Cleisthenes expected his own family to remain close to the center of power, but his reforms soon took on a momentum of their own, deepening the role of the demos while creating new demands for genuine equality throughout public life (isonomia). One factor in this development was internal to the reforms themselves, as adult men gained unprecedented influence through their majorities within the assembly and the law courts.

The second factor was historical. The reforms of Cleisthenes came seventeen years before the invasion of Greece by an enormous Persian army. Against all odds, the Athenian citizen-army helped defeat the Persian attempt to conquer Greece, first on land at the Battle of Marathon (490 BCE), and then more decisively at sea in the Battle of Salamis (480 BCE).

The second of these battles announced the Athenian navy as a major military force a force that was manned by the poorest Athenians, known as thetes. In the aftermath of this great victory, Athens developed a maritime empire that relied heavily on the contribution of the fleet.

This contribution, combined with the wealth of empire, helped to attenuate class struggle in Athens during much of the fifth century and created the conditions for the final strategy employed by the most farsighted aristocrats. These were men like Pericles, who forged his own influence in the middle decades of the century by supporting key demands from the democratic polis.

The rise of democracy entailed a radical departure from the norms of the ancient world. For the first time in recorded history, significant numbers of people made their own decisions. However, the force of this revolution was constrained by a number of important factors:

The resulting class relations were suitably complex. On the one hand, the Athenian citizenry became a unified political elite, making common cause in military campaigns and in the protection of their domestic privileges. On the other hand, class struggle persisted within the citizenry itself as the nobility sought to project their remaining privileges further into the polis, while poorer citizens used their greater numbers to counteract them.

The value system reflected these contradictory class relations in important ways. As it was a society engaged in regular warfare, aret remained the central virtue of Athenian citizens with excellence now tied to ones achievements while fighting for the polis. Citizens were encouraged to conceive of their city-state in semidivine terms. They were expected to fight ferociously in the citizen-army and to see their own success as intimately bound up with success for their compatriots.

To counterbalance these centrifugal forces based on courage and military achievement, the democratic polis also fostered cooperative virtues based on moderation and self-control (sophrosyne). Avoiding hubris became an essential attribute of citizenship, as every citizen was encouraged to act with measure and within fair limits, allowing justice to emerge within a community of political equals.

A second development was a fusion of reason, politics, and social superiority felt by men deliberating in the polis and judging in the law courts. Citizens were expected to listen to an argument, weigh up the evidence, and make their own decisions. The result was a sense of equality among the citizenry mixed with a sense of superiority over everyone else.

Reason (logos) became a defining feature of the democratic polis, while wisdom or the excellence of reason became associated with public speaking in the assembly and the law courts. The result was a set of cardinal virtues that went significantly beyond military prowess: wisdom, courage, prudence, and justice.

Another expression of the connection between politics and reason was the political nature of Greek metaphysics, as philosophers projected the laws of their poleis into the laws of the universe. Replacing the arbitrary judgements of the old aristocracy, Greek legal codes written down and on public display regularized relations among the citizenry, ensuring that justice became objective, universal, and predictable.

The sense of order that resulted from this process was soon writ large in the laws of the universe. Greek thought developed an analogy between the justice of the polis and the justice of the universe a form of cosmic moral order that was present in the souls of men, in the relations of the city, and in the wider pattern of the universe.

A further development was a contest over the nature of this order between representatives of democracy and those aristocratic philosophers who sought a return to more traditional forms of hierarchy. For those in the former camp, the polis was enriched through democratic reforms aimed at creating isonomia a political ideal that simultaneously meant equality in law and a genuinely equal distribution of political power.

Conservative thinkers championed an alternative form of geometric equality that they defined as eunomia. Here the guiding principle was that men are unequal by nature and that those who make proportionately greater contributions to the polis should be afforded proportionately more responsibility for its running.

The latter doctrine was to prove extremely important for Plato as a young aristocrat growing up during the horrors of the Peloponnesian War. Witnessing mass decision-making during the war, Plato, like his maternal relatives, reached the conclusion that democracy was full of sycophants and ignoramuses, who governed through irrational whims rather than genuine knowledge.

He further assumed that democracy upset the natural order of things as it allowed inferior men to control their superiors, often with disastrous consequences. Indeed, the depravity of Athenian democracy was confirmed for Plato when it executed his great mentor Socrates in 399 BCE. Yet when they had their chance to replace this democracy, Platos associates had proven no less depraved, murdering their opponents and tearing up the rule of law.

For Plato, this was evidence of moral degeneration across the state. It also demanded an entirely new basis for political organization one that would be rooted in divine first principles of ultimate reality. It was to achieve this task that Plato undertook his most famous work, The Republic.

Platos earliest dialogues use his master Socrates to highlight the ignorance of the masses. Socrates typically engages a fellow Athenian in a process of elenchus, a process of questioning and answering that exposes error in their common-sense explanation, allowing the interlocuters to move closer to the truth. However, the results often lead to aporia (perplexity), as the truth proves elusive under the scrutiny of the Socratic method.

To escape this perplexity, Plato turns in his middle-period dialogues to divine inspiration in his theory of forms. He argues that while the material world is subject to generation and degeneration, the ultimate ground of this world its ontological first principle is a realm of perfect, eternal, and absolute forms. The phenomena of everyday life are best understood as imperfect manifestations of divinely sanctioned structuring principles responsible for the order exhibited throughout the visible cosmos.

Knowledge of these forms is essential for understanding how an intelligent logos has arranged the visible cosmos into a hierarchy of beings, reflecting the hierarchy of the forms themselves. It is also essential for ruling justly, as those who spend their time contemplating the form of justice will be determined to see its pattern imitated in society as well.

The Ionian materialists had assumed that the order of the universe was immanent within matter itself. Politically, this had egalitarian connotations, as everything results from patterns of material necessity rather than divine intervention. Since human beings are all part of this material necessity, there is nothing to differentiate them from each other.

Plato, following Pythagoras, rejects the metaphysics of the Ionian philosopher Anaximander as incapable of explaining the obvious intelligence underpinning the material world. Matter is base and disordered without a higher form to give it structure. This is the basis for his reactionary metaphysics, as everything becomes part of a hierarchy of being.

Indeed, Platos most famous dialogue attempts to elicit justice in the city and soul by grounding it in the form of justice revealed as divine and eternal. To achieve this, he creates a famous analogy between the inner lives of men and their outer lives as citizens between the relations of the parts making up their souls and the relations of the classes making up their city. In both cases, justice emerges from the proportionate ordering of the parts within a hierarchically structured totality.

There are six principles to this ordering process that ensure justice will emerge:

Platos first task is to apply this framework to relations in the city. To achieve this, he constructs a thought experiment an ideal city-state with the help of his two aristocratic interlocuters, Glaucon and Adeimantus.

Platos first assumption is his most important one. He assumes that nature makes men and women of different qualities and that these natural differences mean that society must be made up of separate classes, each with their own role within a harmonious totality. His discussion initially focuses on the benefits of economic specialization, arguing that different people are inherently suitable for different activities, as people are not particularly similar to one another, but have a wide variety of natures.

In this context, Plato begins with the majority of citizens who spend their days in different occupations. Their work will provide resources for the polis, but unlike the farmer-hoplites in democratic Athens, they will not be responsible for any military activity. Plato envisages a fully professional army freed from the demands of manual labor, following the model of Sparta.

However, he also assumes a further division within the auxiliaries to ensure that those who have a philosophers love of knowledge become the rational element within the state, while those who are naturally courageous take direction from the guardians proper. This leaves us with a class of producers, a class of auxiliaries, and a class of guardians. It soon becomes clear that the thrust of Platos argument is not about economic specialization at all but rather is designed to erect a rigid class system, with the majority excluded from access to political decision-making and the means of violence.

Historically, warrior-aristocrats tended to use their control of violence to further their own sectional interests. But Plato believes that this can be avoided if those with the most rational natures train the auxiliaries to work within proper bounds to show courage and ferocity when meeting the enemy, but gentleness and honor when dealing with their fellow citizens.

At this point, Plato makes the fundamental political argument of the Republic, which is that a harmonious community can only emerge when there is proportionality within the social totality, with all three classes working together for the good of the whole. Organized through the wisdom of the guardians, the ideal city exhibits a form of hierarchical order that allows all of the parts to reach their potential.

The wisdom of the guardians will be complemented by the courage of the warriors. Workers will display moderation by accepting that they have no business in ruling while their superiors will act moderately by ensuring that their rule will be in the interests of all. The overall result will exhibit justice and morality as every part receives the amount of honor and responsibility commensurate with its natural ability and social training:

When each of the three classes the ones that work for a living, the auxiliaries, and the guardians performs its own function and does its own job . . . then this is justice and makes the community a moral one.

Accepting the four cardinal virtues of the Athenian city-state, Plato has given them an aristocratic twist. For the Athenian citizen, all four virtues make up the excellence of his character. For Plato, on the other hand, wisdom is possessed by only one class of citizens, courage by another.

These two groups make up the ruling classes, with moderation and justice formed around a compact between rulers and ruled. Members of one class will accept their subjection, while members of the other will rule them justly.

The next step in the argument is to draw an analogy between the well-functioning city and the well-functioning soul. Having shown that a just society contains three classes arranged into a hierarchic totality, Plato insists that there are three analogous parts to the soul, with reason mirroring the role of the guardians, passion that of the auxiliaries, and desire that of the workers.

The central argument in his discussion of the state is that justice requires all three classes to work together. Here we find Plato arguing that a well-ordered soul can only flourish when each of its parts does its appropriate function and allows the others to do the same.

Reason, for Plato, is the highest faculty in the human soul. It is the souls connection with divine intelligence and, as such, it is the only part capable of understanding the good of the whole. Its role is to order the parts into proportionate relations so that goodness will emerge.

To achieve this, it must enlist the passions as its loyal auxiliary as its emotional drive to ensure that each human being can live a well-ordered life. Rational people successfully recruit their passions to ensure that only those desires that facilitate their long-term flourishing (eudaemonia) will be acceded to. Desire plays the part of the worker in Platos analogy, as the lowest, most inferior, and most numerous faculty within the soul.

In this schema, well-regulated desires have their proper place in the well-lived life. However, when they are left unchecked, desires have the potential to overstep their boundaries, undermining proportionality and throwing a harmonious totality into disorder. Unruly desires, like unruly workers, try to dominate and rule over things which they are not equipped by their hereditary status to rule over, and so plunge the whole of everyones life into chaos.

At this point, the two parts of Platos analogy can be brought into harmonious alignment. Nature makes different kinds of people with different kinds of souls. Those with the most rational souls and the right education will have wisdom enough to organize their own souls and the classes in the polis into mathematically proportionate relations modeled on the pattern of justice evident in the forms.

Those who lack sufficient wisdom and social training can still play their part by allowing the guardians to temper unruly desires and make political decisions for the good of everyone. At its core, this is a sophisticated version of Solons eunomia referenced above.

Plato has accepted the centrality of equality in the democratic polis but once again given it an aristocratic twist. Men who contribute proportionately more should be rewarded with proportionately more. Treating men who are equal in capacity as equals is justice everything else is injustice.

The neoconservative philosopher Leo Strauss once described The Republic as the harshest possible indictment of the reigning democracy . . . which was ever uttered. Strauss was no democrat either, but his point is well made when viewed in the light of Platos metaphysics.

Rooting his analysis in the nature of the divine, Plato argues that democracy represents a disastrous attempt to overturn the hierarchic order of reality itself. Distinctions between higher and lower, better and worse, are woven into the fabric of reality a reality that is also mathematical in structure, containing proportionate relations among its parts.

Justice relies on the different parts getting their due, with mathematically proportionate relations among the hierarchy of forms, the hierarchy of citizens, and the hierarchy of soul constituents. Justice in the state requires the distribution of relevant political goods so that those who contribute the most receive the most in return.

Plato contrasts this model to democracy, which insists on treating naturally unequal men as if they were equal. This gives such inferior types more than they are morally entitled to receive, destroying the proportionality that underpins justice, and creating chaos in every domain.

People in democracies laud their freedom and equality. Yet for Plato, this masks a deeper servility as disordered men and women get pushed from pillar to post by desires that enslave them. Chaos in their internal lives in compounded by chaos in their city-state. The result is the proliferation of sycophants in public life, as demagogues peddle their wares among ignorant masses.

A second result is the defilement of philosophy, as those who cannot hope to understand the nature of the forms nevertheless encroach on the work of those who do. Respecting the hierarchic ordering of the universe, aristocratic rule not only expresses the natural order of things. It is morally just and supremely good.

Plato has therefore made class rule universally beneficial on a threefold basis. He has presented reality as infused with a reason that operates behind the backs of ordinary people; he has presented his own class as the inheritors of this reason, once they have been reformed in line with philosophy; and he has utilized his metaphysics to sanctify class rule as the reflection of a deeper cosmic justice.

The Republic rationalizes class as part of the natural order of things. Its enduring influence and success was surely linked to the death of Athenian democracy a mere twenty-five years after the death of Plato himself.

See more here:
Plato's Philosophy Is an Aristocratic Attack on Democracy and ... - Jacobin magazine