What should modern independent India be and how can it get there? | EconomyNext – EconomyNext

This excerpt features the introduction to Mark Hagers recently published book, Elusive Ideology: Religion and Socialism in Modern Indian Thought, along with the books first chapter on the foundational work of the prototypical Hindu socialist, Vivekananda.

This is a study of what could be called the ambivalent relationship between religion and socialism in modern Indian thought. It highlights both congruences and antagonisms between religious and socialist ideas in a handful of leading thinkers. It explores problems they encounter attempting to reconcile religious and socialist concerns. It emphasizes the general character of these problems by highlighting recurrence of common themes. It also explores differences among these thinkers and suggests that those variations create a pattern of distinguishable responses to a unified set of concerns. India is sometimes not recalled these days as a haven for socialist thinking. Look again.

Attempts to restate traditional religious ideas and to juxtapose them with Western socialist ideas are so pervasive in modern Indian thought as to constitute perhaps its most distinctive and unifying characteristic. In varying ways, leading figures weave together interpretations of socialist ideas and traditional religious ideas, often so as to imagine social institutions and practices where spiritual values and economic organization might be mutually reinforcing.

It is not strange that socialism and religion should have an ambivalent relationship. On the one hand, their orientations tend to diverge. Socialism concerns itself with problems of material production, while religion devalues material concerns for spiritual ones. On the other hand, socialism generally and religion often translate concerns for human fulfillment into social visions of solidarity-sentiments of interdependence between private and general well-being. This resemblance sets religion and socialism apart from liberalism and capitalism, for example, which in their social theories typically de-emphasize solidarity. The commonality of religion and socialism tends to bring them into contact, but contrasting orientations can make that contact a tense one.

Ambivalence between religion and socialism has been especially acute in India, due largely to experiences of imperial subjugation. In the late nineteenth century, resistance to imperialism spawned a set of attitudes, including socialist and religious ones, which could be called the first Indian radicalism.

Imperialism, as it seemed, was first of all an experience of economic subservience and exploitation. The rise and triumph of industrial capitalism in Great Britain struck many as dependent on economic dominance over India, the impoverishment of which fueled Britains enrichment. Indian thinkers learned to focus on capitalisms negative features. In imagining eventual liberation, they strove to imagine a system of non-exploitative production. They called it socialism.

Imperial subjugation was secondly an experience of cultural anxiety and doubt. Indian thinkers inhabited a twilight zone, feeling the attractions and repulsions of both Western and Indian cultures. Dominance of the West, combined with the apparently advanced nature of Western ideas, prompted an impulse to denigrate Indian culture. At the same time, dreams of liberation from imperial rule prompted impulses toward denigrating Western culture and exalting India.

The case for prompt liberation gained strength from asserting that Western culture was harmful to Indias well-being but weakened under any sense that Western culture was superior or necessary to Indias progress. Advocacy of Indian culture over Western culture involved sympathy toward religious themes.

Thus, radical resistance to British rule commonly linked up with advocacy of both socialism and traditional religion. Less radical anti-imperialism, by contrast, generally went with more muted economic critiques and less fervent allegiance to religion. This contrast exemplified itself in turn-of-the-century schism in the nationalist movement between Extremists and Moderates. There was generally more of both explicit socialism and religious preoccupation in viewpoints of Extremists such as Tilak, Aurobindo, Bipin Chandra Pal, and Lala Lajpat Rai than with Moderates like Ranade and Gokhale.

Modern Indian radicalism then, originated with intense symbiosis of religion and socialism, a symbiosis that ironically remained ambivalent. Born from experiences of imperial subjugation, this ambivalent symbiosis later fed upon the increasingly negative example of Soviet socialism. Some admired early Soviet developments while others frowned from the start on communist atheism and violence. Criticism mounted as the Soviet system grew increasingly autocratic, bureaucratic, cynical, and repressive. This did not, however, induce leading Indian thinkers to ignore problems of Western hegemony or to embrace the developed West as savior of the free world. They developed instead a critique of both Western and Soviet systems culminating in Nehrus sponsorship of a Non-Aligned Movement for the Third World. This Third World consciousness reinforced India in its anti-imperial impulse to seek out virtues in its own heritage. Rejection of Soviet socialism struck some as leaving no option but to develop a socialism rooted in Indias distinctive heritage of flourishing religious sensibility.

For several reasons then, juxtaposition of religion and socialism lies at the heart of modern Indian thoughts most characteristic failures and achievements. It can therefore stand as an axis around which to interpret that thought as a unified intellectual tradition. This tradition drills down on a distinctive problematic: to interweave socialist ideas with Indian religious ideas in pursuit of a sound and worthwhile ideology. By problematic, I mean a persistent pattern of interrelated questions defining the subject matter for a system of inquiry. By ideology, I mean simply some picture of a better society combined with ideas on how to achieve it. As will become clear, the problematic explored here is an elastically-defined intellectual universe. It is by no means a unified answer to a single question, but rather a cluster of questions and proposed answers driven by a distinct and persisting sense of moral and intellectual unease.

By framing my analysis in terms of a problematic, I hope both highlight its centrality and to suggest a certain logic in its unfolding. Particular controversy may emerge from my treatment of thinkers within the problematic as failures or successes. By failure and success, I mean something quite particular: the degree to which various thinkers, in their deployment of religious and socialist ideas, manage to remedy the complementary weaknesses of each. Religions typical weakness as ideology is failure to visualize practical institutions to embody and express its values in all spheres of activity. Religion is often especially weak in reconciling aspirational values with demands of productive activity. Socialisms frequent weakness lies in failure to investigate and cultivate spiritual virtues needed in any worthwhile system of socialized production. Socialisms frequent and erroneous conceit holds that achieving socialized production-common and roughly equal ownership of productive resources-itself ensures moral regeneration. Even when it does focus on spiritual regeneration it often treats those concerns as secondary to socialized production.

Modern Indian thinkers have tried to steer a middle course avoiding typical failings of both socialism and religion. They by and large reject what may be called materialist socialism, which imagines either that right economic organization must precede cultivation of fraternal social relations or will yield such relations automatically afterward. These thinkers also by and large try to avoid what may be called pure religious ideology, which imagines that spiritual transformation can usher in a harmonious and just society prior to or without need of transformed productive organization. With one interesting exception they grope to articulate an ideology of mutual dependence and reinforcement between spiritual growth and socialist productive arrangements.

Within this problematic success lies especially in emergence and refinement of Gandhian socialism. Gandhian socialism maintains a simultaneous focus on cultivating virtue and socializing productive arrangements. Widespread practice of moral virtue and progressive socialization require and reinforce each other, pursued in tandem not isolation. These insights, crucial to Gandhian socialism, characterize the entire tradition examined here, with Ambedkar as the interesting exception. What distinguishes Gandhian socialism from failures within this tradition is its clarity in perceiving the issues and coherence in solutions offered. In a sense, therefore, this is a study of the background and development of Gandhian socialism. In contrast to many Gandhian studies, it seeks to locate Gandhi in a particular intellectual-historical framework. It seeks to understand the context of ideas in which Gandhis thought evolved as well as the pivotal impact of his thought upon that context.

Part I examines Vivekanandas thought as the problematics first full-blown articulation. The protean character of this thought will be evident throughout the study as it explores themes, problems and vicissitudes that Vivekananda first raises somewhat awkwardly.

Part II explores failures within the problematic: formulations which, though steeped in its peculiar concerns, resolve those concerns in ways not conducive to innovative thought and progressive action. Part II classifies these failures in terms of differing attitudes toward the Hindu tradition. Bhagavan Das formulates a backward-looking Hindu socialist ideology based on the specific classical social scheme set out in Manu, the ancient text of legal and religious orthodoxy. Bipin Chandra Pal and Sri Aurobindo, by contrast, formulate forward-looking Hindu socialisms, de-emphasizing Manus specific framework and stressing instead notions of social order they find implicit in certain Hindu themes. While Aurobindo emphasizes Advaita, inquiry into the non-dual or non-divided nature of reality. Pal, stresses Bhakti, theistic devotionalism. B. R. Ambedkar, finally, represents complete rejection of Hindu tradition as any source of progressive social ideas. Though he repudiates Hinduism, he maintains identification with Indian spiritual culture by embracing and interpreting Buddhism, treating it as chief historical antagonist to Hindu social values.

For differing reasons, all these formulations represent dead ends within the problematic. Though rich with interesting and provocative conceptualizations, they lack the ideological fecundity of Gandhis thought. In various ways, thinkers examined in Part II paint themselves into ideological corners.

Part III inspects Gandhis thought, focusing especially on the evolution and revision of certain key ideas. It highlights how, despite serious problems in his thought, Gandhi lays the foundation for a self-consistent and plausible, innovative, and progressive theory of a worthwhile society and how to build it. Though Gandhis concept of wealth trusteeship is unpromising, two corollaries of his non-violent philosophy become cornerstones of Indias distinctive political vision: Gandhian socialism. One is sarvodaya, construction of egalitarian village communities. The other is satyagraha, non-violent confrontation as method of social change.

Parts IV and V trace the impact of Gandhis ideas upon Indian socialists rooted in Marxism. Here lies the emergence of a distinctive school of thought that can be called Gandhian socialism. Part IV explores partial Gandhian socialism by way of Asoka Mehta, Narendra Deva and Jawaharlal Nehru. Partial implies not inferior thought, but rather a somewhat piece-meal way of fusing Gandhian notions with socialist ones.

Part V explores thorough Gandhian socialism by way of Ramanohar Lohia and J. P. Narayan. These two differ from those in Part IV by the self-consciousness and ambitiousness with which they set about articulating a Gandhian socialism. They are also distinct in their strong emphases on religious themes, issues and ideas.

The Conclusion briefly considers some previously unaddressed questions on Hindu-Muslim confict and on the emergence, shortfalls, limits and significance of Gandhian socialism. There are two reasons for study of modern Indian thought in terms of the patterned problematic outlined here. It serves to clarify the distinctive concerns and ambitions of the thinkers involved, both individually and collectively. It also augments our own thinking about social matters, underscoring crucial issues and making accessible some serious reflection on them. The studys ultimate purpose is to emphasize interdependence of the material and the spiritual in social matters. This theme raises anlogies both Marxist and theological that may warrant brief comment.

A Marxist analogy arises from my bisection of social matters into a material realm of productivity and a spiritual realm of religion, culture, and values. This may recall Marxs distinction of economic base from ideocultural superstructure. Marx sees causal linkage from productive arrangements to religious and cultural values. The tradition explored here departs from dogmatic versions of that paradigm, ones that portray ideocultural superstructure as causally determined by a dominant material base. To thinkers examined here, such views underestimate both possibilities for ideological change within an existing productive order and the necessity of such change in creating new ones.

The theme of spiritual-material interdependence may also bring to mind a theological analogy: incarnation. Gandhis thought implicitly entails a theory of incarnation-penetration of the material by the spiritual. For Gandhi, incarnation is no single event or series of events, but rather an ongoing transfiguration of the material by the spiritual, through which human affairs grow progressively moralized. This spiritualizing process reaches into the material sphere of production and presses for moral transformation there. Incarnation thereby embodies spiritual values in the material sphere, replacing exploitational arrangements by moralized ones. Gandhis thought rebukes doctrines of incarnation that fail to seek moralized productive arrangements.

Part 1

Origins of a problematic

Vivekananda: Socialism and the Reconceptualization of Hindu Religion

Uninvited walk-on rock star at the World Parliament of Religions, Swami Vivekananda (1863-1902) was born in Calcutta with the given name Narendranath Dutt. He was the son of a successful attorney. In 1881, during his college education in Calcutta, Vivekananda first encountered the ecstatic mystical prophet Ramakrishna. Vivekanandas relationship with Ramakrishna deepened after Vivekanandas college education, upon the death of Vivekanandas father in 1884.

Between 1884 and 1893, Vivekananda divided his time among his discipleship to Ramakrishna, work at various jobs to support his family, and wanderings throughout India. In 1893, he addressed Chicagos World Parliament of Religions, where his speech brought him instant celebrity. He toured the United States lecture circuit until 1895, then travelled by way of England, continental Europe and Ceylon (Sri Lanka) back to India, arriving in 1897. It was in 1897 that Vivekananda launched a social service organization known as the Ramakrishna Mission. In 1899, he voyaged again to the West, returning to India fatigued and ill the following year. He thereafter remained in India, lecturing and writing insofar as his health permitted until his death.

His journey to the West in 1893 represented a mission unprecedented among Indian social reformers. He sought both to propagate Indian religious ideas and to secure funding for relief programs targeting the plight of Indias downtrodden masses. His subsequent shuttling between India and the West exemplified a turn in modern Indian sensibilities, and his writings mark a new era in Indian thought.

Throughout most of the nineteenth century, Indian thinkers had investigated a broad range of religious and social issues, motivated by desire to purge Hindu society of beliefs and practices inappropriate to contemporary challenges or to their conceptions of Hinduisms essential genius. Arguments flared and movements emerged in a surge of visionary activity unprecedented since the days of medieval Bhakti. Issues various and vital demanded attention: the meaning or meaninglessness of ritual, the true nature of caste, the oppression and liberation of women, for example. It remained, however, for Vivekananda to focus on one of Indias most glaring ills: poverty, degradation and subjugation among most of Indias vast population.

I am a socialist proclaimed Vivekananda, the first major Indian social thinker to do so. He devotes great attention to the misery of Indias masses. No Indian thinker before him had stressed, as he did, urgent need to eradicate mass poverty. After Vivekananda, no Indian thinker could ignore issues of poverty, exploitation and socialism.

It was not merely the fact but also the manner of this new concern that made Vivekanandas career paradigmatic. His travels between India and the West manifested fervor to forge some synthesis of Indian spiritual and Western material cultures. The way forward for India and perhaps all humanity lay in achieving a progressive material culture harmonizing rather than conflicting with Indian spirituality. Vivekanandas dream was to become the dream of an entire era.

THE AMBIGUOUS SIGNIFICANCE OF SOCIAL ACTION

One striking feature of Vivekanandas thought is its ambivalence on the religious meaning of progressive social action. Vivekananda pays official allegiance to certain classical Indian conceptions of religious life. The ultimate religious task, he claims, is personal spiritual liberation, conceived as escape from a meaningless conventional world into a transcendental dimension of awareness. Escape from the conventional world is, among other things, an escape from society, conceived as a realm of transient, illusory and ultimately meaningless relationships. He rejects the notion of social progress: how could there be progress in such a transient and meaningless realm? The balance of social ill and good remains forever constant, despite manifold apparent changes. Social evil and social good reflect aspects of worldly maya, matters of illusion and ultimate irrelevance from the standpoint of true spiritual insight.

Why then should anyone engage in any kind of social action? Vivekananda suggests that the value of social action lies exclusively in contributing to personal spiritual liberation. The most captivating aspect of conventional reality or maya is preoccupation with concerns of ones worldly self. Social action entailing personal sacrifice helps the individual achieve liberation from such bonds of worldly ego-centricity. Vivekananda repeatedly speaks of the world as a moral gymnasium in which individuals can strengthen their spiritual natures through exercises of self-sacrificial social action.

Vivekananda seems on the surface unaware of any contradiction in advocating self-sacrifice for a society that cannot thereby benefit. Self-sacrifice implies a preference for a wider social good over a narrower personal one. This makes no sense if the possibility of wider social good is denied.

Though Vivekananda may not see the contradiction logically, he surely feels it existentially. He could not devote so much concern to alleviating social miseries without feeling positive transformation to be both possible and intrinsically worthwhile. He cannot, despite himself, resist the notion that the very pinnacle of religious life lies in social action. I have realized he writes at one point, that altruistic service only is religion, the restare madness-even it is wrong to hanker after ones own salvation. (sic). It is rare for Vivekananda to voice this viewpoint so explicitly. Far more typical are comments that [O]ne must completely mold ones religious life in solitude, and that All the work you dois done for your own benefit. He endorses classical notions of a sharp divide between social engagement and the highest religious life. Occasional comments, however, along with the sheer scope of his social concern, indicate Vivekananda wrestling with radical notions: that the true meaning of religion is society and that the highest religious life lies in working for progressive social change.

SOCIAL CHANGE BY AND FOR THE DOWNTRODDEN

Vivekanandas writings contain curious passages in which he rails against Indian advocates of social reform. Such passages at first appear reactionary, but in fact they represent a radical new approach to Indian social change. The problem with so-called social reformers, according to Vivekananda, is that they merely criticize specific ills in hopes of provoking changes in habits. Vivekananda finds this approach nave: people do not change their practices just because they have been plausibly criticized. A few men who think that certain things are evil will not make a nation move, he writes.

Social change, he thinks, can be catalyzed, but not engineered. Masses of people must, through their own experience and reflection, create new ways of organizing their lives. True social reform requires augmenting the power of the masses to reflect and to act. Vivekananda writes:

It takes time, quite a long time, to make a healthy, strong, public opinion which will solve its own problems The whole problem of social reform, therefore, resolves itself into this: Where are those who want reform? Make them first First educate the nation First create the power, the sanction from which the law will so ring.

The masses require education and power. Hence, for Vivekananda, meaningful reform requires revolutionizing societys fundamental order, an order of hierarchical exploitation:

To the reformers I will point out that I am a greater reformer than any one of them. They want to reform only little bits. I want root-and-branch reform. Where we differ is in the Method Most of the reforms that have been agitated for during the past century have been ornamental. Every one of these reforms only touches the first two castes, and no other. The question of widow marriage would not touch seventy per cent of the Indian women, and all such questions only reach the higher castes of Indian people who are educated, mark you, at the expense of the masses. But that is no reformation. You must go down to the basis of the thing, to the very root of the matter. That is what I call radical reform.

Vivekananda seldom misses an opportunity to emphasize the plight of Indias poor or to condemn systems of exploitation that oppress them. The one thing that is at the root of all evils in India is the condition of the poor, he writes, as he describes their condition:

(C)lusters of huts, with crumbling mud-walls (M)oving aboutemaciated figures of young and old in tattered rags, whose faces bear deep-cut lines of the despair and poverty of yearsthe pitiful gaze of lustreless eyes of the hunger-stricken Devastation by violent plague and cholera; malaria eating into the very vitals of the nation; starvation and semi-starvation as second nature; the Kurukshetra (battlefield) of malady and misery A conglomeration of three hundred million souls, resembling men only in appearance, crushed out of life by being downtrodden by their own people and by foreign nations

Vivekananda points to the caste system and imperialism, priest power and foreign conquest, as twin causes of mass impoverishment. In Marx-like fashion, he analyzes both caste and imperialism as systems of exploitation in which the downtrodden produce wealth but do not own or enjoy it. He writes of the tyranny of the higher castes, in which:

The cultivator got almost nothing The protector came to be known as the king; he who took the commodities from one place to another was the merchant. These two did not produce anything-but still snatched away the best part of things and made themselves fat by virtually reaping most of the fruit of the cultivators toil and labor.

Elsewhere, he writes of the peasant, the shoemaker, the sweeper, and such other lower classes of India, who through the ages have been producing the entire wealth of the land, while non-producing classes have taken the substantial part of the fruits of their labor.

A similar analysis applies to British rule, of which he writes the main idea is blood-sucking. Indian labor and produce could support the entire nation in material comfort, if the whole thing is not taken off from them. Instead, India suffers at the hands of the British, who have carried away with them millions of our money, while our people have starved by villages and provinces. Vivekananda argues that though famine seldom visits parts of India still free from British rule, it occurs as the inevitable consequence of exploitation in British-ruled India.

Keen to alleviate the plight of Indias poor masses, Vivekananda organizes resources and activities of the Ramakrishna Mission. He urges followers to devote heart and soul to this one duty-the duty of raising the masses of India. Borrowing from ancient religious notions of foreswearing normal pursuits in favor of spiritual seeking, he urges a life of sannayasa (renunciation) for his followers, who should subdue all private desires in order to serve the masses: Vow, then, to devote your whole lives to the cause of these three hundred millions.

Less than clear as to what activities these sannayasins of service should pursue, Vivekananda focuses most concretely on education. He imagines bands of disinterested sannyasins, bent on doing good to others, going from village to village, disseminating education and seeking in various ways to better the condition of all The instruction should emphasize religion, as well as the arts of life. His images of instruction to offer seem sketchy:

Make an organized plan. A few cameras, some maps, globes, and some chemicals, etc., are needed. The next thing you want is a big hut. Then you must get together a number of poor, indigent folk. Having done all this, show them pictures to teach them astronomy, geography, etc., and preach Sri Ramakrishna to them.

Along with abstract learning should go enhancement of productive skills: the discovery of new avenues of production through exertions aided by Western science, enabling villagers to produce food and clothing for themselves.

Vivekananda imagines that such efforts will spark mass movements so as to revolutionize the whole country. Villagers will join the educational movement, accelerating expansion of knowledge and problem-solving capacity. Vivekanandas philosophy of change includes almost no analysis of specific problems or how to solve them. He explains his entire approach with a formula: (E)ducate our people, so that they may be able to solve their own problems. There is undoubted navet in this vision of mass liberation through mere education. In discerning the need for village mobilization, however, Vivekananda points out an approach which, in the hands of Gandhi and some of his followers, becomes a rich philosophy of transformation.

Exploitation, Vivekananda thinks, will ultimately cease with the triumph of socialism. In Marx-like fashion, he associates socialism with rule by the laboring class or Shudras. Like Marx, he sees the triumph of labor historically destined: (A) time will come whenthe Shudra class with their Shudrahoodwill gain absolute supremacy in every society. Again like Marx, he sees labors impending triumph as the crowning phase in an historical succession of rule by different classes. For Vivekananda, these correspond to the four varnas (caste groupings) of classical Indian social thought: (H)uman society is in turn governed by the four castes-the priests, the soldiers, the traders, and the laborers. He thinks of capitalism as rule by the commercial or Vaishya caste, awful in its silent crushing and blood-sucking power associates British imperial rule with Vaishya hegemony.

Last will come the laborer rule, writes Vivekananda, and he applauds this as the end to economic exploitation. Yet he is less than fully enthusiastic about this triumph of socialism. He sees socialism as a system or doctrine with something important missing. I am a socialist not because I think it is a perfect system, but half a loaf is better than no bread. Nowhere does he articulate in detail what he means by the half a loaf that socialism fails to provide. He indicates, however, that socialism-though essential from a purely economic standpoint-lacks moral or spiritual dimensions crucial to worthwhile social life. Of socialism he writes: Its advantages will be the distribution of physical comforts-its disadvantages, (perhaps) the lowering of culture. By the lowering of culture, he means decline in morality, which is decline in essential religion:

Everything goes to show that Socialismis coming on the boards. The people will certainly want the satisfaction of their material needs, less work, no oppression, no war, more food. What guarantee have we that this civilization will last, unless it is based on religion, on the goodness of man? Depend on it, religion goes to the root of the matter. If it is right, all is right.

Vivekananda insists that ancient Vedantic (philosophically scriptural) Hinduism is the right religion for socialism: (E)qualising theories must have a spiritual basis, and that spiritual basis is the Vedanta only. To understand this, we need to explore his interpretation of Vedanta. This will prove helpful when we touch on other thinkers as well.

KANTIAN ADVAITA AND SPIRITUALIZED SOCIALISM

Vivekanandas Vedanta centers on Advaita, the philosophy of universal non-dualism, explanation of which occupies much of Vivekanandas effort. It is crucial to understand the Advaitic doctrine of selfhood as Vivekananda interprets it.

Advaita, he observes, asserts a non-dual theory of selfhood. There may appear to be a plenitude of selves in the world, but this is an illusion. There is, in reality, only one unitary and universal Self, in which all the many separate and particular selves merely participate.

Classical Advaita, it has often been claimed, makes no strong pronouncements in ethics and morals. The goal is private salvation, not the well-being of others. Liberation, insight on the non-duality of Selfhood, consists in gnosis, or knowledge, not moral action. Vivekanandas striking reinterpretation links the Advaitic doctrine of Selfhood with a theory of morality.

Morality for Vivekananda concerns two basic questions: what is moral action? and why should one practice it? His simple answer to the first question is: (T)he only definition that can be given of morality is that: That which is selfish is immoral, and that which is unselfish is moral. His answer to the second question involves Advaitic interpretation of selfish and unselfish. Selfishness, concern for private wellbeing over general well-being, self-defeatingly posits an illusory, separate, and particular self, over the true and universal Self. In reality, however, there is no well-being apart from general well-being. Unselfishness pursues general well-being, the only true well-being. We learn why one should act morally: because only moral action promotes true well-being. True well-being, general well-being, advances only through unselfish action.

Borrowing from classical Advaitic philosophy, Vivekananda explains how humans naturally but mistakenly identify their well-being with illusory private selfhood. An illusion of isolated and particular selfhood arises from entanglement of universal Selfhood in the material world. There the Self inhabits particular bodies creating illusion of distinction and separation. The universal Self makes contact with nature through the sense experience of these illusory selves. This entanglement with nature, the sense experience of illusory separate selves, is root cause of selfishness. Well-being mistakenly seems identified with the bodys sensual enjoyment in the world of nature.

If pursuit of private well-being is illusion, it is also unfreedom. Selfishness is a life of slavery to sense experience, desire, and satisfaction. Vivekanandas interpretation of Advaita owes much to Kant. For Vivekananda as for Kant, morality and freedom are one and the same. Like Kant, Vivekananda conceives of nature as a realm of determination and unfreedom. In nature, events follow laws of causality that allow no variation. There is therefore no freedom in the world of nature. Human beings, through their bodies, inhabit this enslaved realm, part of nature and therefore subject to determined causality. Human action tied to nature through the body can never be free. In particular, human action is unfree if determined by sensual imperatives of the illusory separate self. Sensually determined action, selfishness, unfreedom: these are equivalent.

Freedom, by contrast, lies in control of the sensual passions by the will, which is spiritual. Freedom lies in action not dictated by nature. Free action is moral action, aimed at general rather than private well-being. That action is moral which frees us from the bondage of matter and vice versa, writes Vivekananda. Pursuit of private well-being can yield only frustration because sensual desire is ultimately insatiable, only inflamed by temporary satisfaction. Desire is infinite, its fulfillment limited, Vivekananda writes. The satisfaction of desire only increases it, as oil poured on fire but makes it burn more fiercely.

To Vivekananda, true well-being implies a liberation from nature. This requires restraint upon sensual passions and material enjoyment. As with Kant, freedom requires self-restraint, exercise of power by will over nature. No freedom without renunciation, writes Vivekananda. As also with Kant, this freedom is equivalent to morality.

Vivekanandas interpretation of Advaita provides socialism with an appropriate spiritual basis. Socialism seeks an end to exploitation. Exploitation and social inequality, thinks Vivekananda, are ultimately rooted in selfishness, slavery to inherently limitless material desire:

There is a limit to the working power of human beings, but no limit to desire; so we strive to get hold of the working power of others and enjoy the fruits of their labors, escaping work ourselves.

By explaining roots of selfishness in Advaitic terms as spiritual error and its consequences in Marxist terms as drive to command the labor of others, Vivekananda shows the mutual relevance of Vedantic religion and socialism.

To Vivekananda, the main shortcoming of most socialist doctrine lies in failure to identify and attack exploitation at its root: spiritual error. Advaita, urging restraint on material passions and preference for general well-being, attacks the root of exploitation and motivates effort to build a socialist order. Sannyasins of service exemplify Advaitic renunciation as they work for social transformation.

If Advaita is crucial to actualizing socialism, the reverse is also true. Vivekananda tirelessly insists on the emptiness of spiritual values not exemplified and fostered by concrete social institutions. He writes, That society is the greatest, where the highest truths become practical. His thought weakens, however, when he tries to imagine the incarnation of non-exploitation in practical arrangements.

AMBIVALENT SOCIOLOGY

Vivekanandas exploration of the practical consists primarily of scattered commentaries on Indian and Western social arrangements. The bulk of these consists of two overlapping types: 1) contrasts of Indian and Western society; and 2) discussions of caste.

Societies, holds Vivekananda, can be distinguished from each other based on particular aptitudes for exploring and solving different sorts of problems. Hence every society displays a distinctive genius accounting for much of its overall character. To Vivekananda, the crucial distinction lies in contrast between Indian and Western societies. Indian society, he urges, is essentially spiritual, Western society primarily materialistic. India specializes in spiritual progress, the West in material progress.

Western materialism, thinks Vivekananda, inevitably fosters both exploitation and dissatisfaction. He sees Western capitalism as the apotheosis of exploitation and dissatisfaction rooted in a materialist approach to life. Capitalist wealth has not solved the problem of want, but only made it keener. Pursuit of material enjoyment brings no satisfaction, but only a greater quantum of desire. Accumulations of capital and productive power merely expand the power of selfish impulses. Hence, capitalism achieves record heights of exploitation and antagonism:

The material tyranny is tremendous. The wealth and power of a country are in the hands of a few men who do not work but manipulate the work of millions of human beings. By this power they can deluge the whole earth with blood

Vivekananda maintains that the West cannot alleviate this appalling state of affairs through its own spiritual resources. Many Westerners, he maintains, have grown weary of the competition, the struggle, the brutality of their commercial civilization. He presumably has socialism in mind when he writes that they are looking forward towards something better, calling for political and social changes as panacea for capitalist ills.

Vivekananda finds little promise in what he sees as the narrowly institutional approach of most socialists, who expect progress from mere political or social manipulation. It is spiritual culture and ethical culture, he thinks, that the West needs in order to remedy its civilizational defects. Only India, with its rich reservoir of spiritual culture, can provide Western culture what it needs. The nations of the West are coming to us for spiritual help, he writes. The West must learn from India the conquest of internal nature.

India meanwhile stands in danger of infection by Western materialism. The curse of the West-the senses, has been creeping into India, contaminating Indian culture with luxurious ideals, he writes. India must keep a firm hold on spirituality. To adopt the materializing civilization of the West courts moral ruin.

Despite these moral hazards, Vivekaranda insists that India embrace greater materialism. What is most dangerous is also most necessary. Indias poverty and exploitation cannot be alleviated without massive attention to problems of production:

We talk foolishly against material civilization Material civilization, nay, even luxury, is necessary to create work for the poor. Bread! Bread! India is to be raised, the poor are to be fed, education is to be spread, and the evil of priestcraft is to be removed. No priestcraft, no social tyranny! More bread, more opportunity for everybody.

There is obvious perplexity in Vivekanandas mind as he alternately condemns and praises luxury and material civilization. Socialisms practical requirements clash with its spiritual ones. Vivekananda attempts to resolve this dilemma through formula and conceptual compromise. In order to reap benefits while avoiding pitfalls, he advises that material civilization be adopted in moderate amount: A little of it, perhaps, is good for us. The notion of moderate materialism is a fertile one, but only insofar as it transcends Vivekanandas quick Goldilocks epiphany. Some thinkers explored below improve on this at least somewhat, offering spiritual discussions and productive proposals around themes of moderate materialism. On a related note, Vivekananda imagines a sort of hybrid of India and the West, producing a society progressive both materially and spiritually. Can you make a European society with Indias religion? I believe it is possible, and must be.A blend of Indian spirituality with Western material culture becomes a paradigm for later thinkers. Vivekananda articulates the paradigm but does not go far in applying it.

Vivekanandas dilemmas grow more convoluted when he turns to the issue of caste. Caste, according to Vivekananda, is a system of exploitation. It is also Vedantic religions most prominent social feature. Hence, caste is an obvious embarrassment for asserting Vedantic religion as key antidote to exploitation. The simplest evasion is to deny any link between Advaitic spirituality and caste. In religion, Vivekananda writes, there is no caste; caste is simply a social institution. Caste is nothing more than hereditary division of labor, comparable to networks of trade guilds. It is a mere practical arrangement, devoid of religious meaning. Vivekananda warns that exaggerated ritual aspects of caste have nearly destroyed religion. What more degradation can there be, he writes, than that the greatest minds of a country have been discussing about the kitchen for several hundreds of years, discussing whether I may touch you or you touch me, and what is the penance for this touching! Vivekananda bemoans these bizarre preoccupations:

We are neither Vedantists, most of us now, nor Pauranics, nor Tantrics. We are just Dont touchists. Our religion is in the kitchen. Our God is the cooking pot, and our religion is, Dont touch me, I am holy. If this goes on for another century, every one of us will be in a lunatic asylum.

Vivekananda wavers, however, in separating religion and caste. He seeks in various ways to portray caste as an element in Vedantic religions moral and anti-exploitative genius. He portrays caste, for example, as an orientation in social life toward general well-being in communities rather than private well-being as individuals. Caste therefore exerts a moralizing influence in contrast with Western cultures encouragement of selfishness:

You Western people are individualistic. I want to do this thing because I like it; I will elbow everyone. Why? Because I like to. I want my own satisfaction So what is the basis of Indias social order? It is the caste law. I am born for the caste, I live for the caste. Born in the caste, the whole life must be lived according to caste regulation. In other wordsthe Western man is born individualistic, while the Hindu is socialistic-entirely socialistic.

In discouraging selfish individualism, the socialist spirit of caste protects the weak from exploitation. This it does by fostering cooperative rather than antagonistic economic relationships:

Competition-cruel, cold, and heartless-is the law of Europe. Our law is caste-the breaking of competition, checking its forces, mitigating its cruelties

The notion of caste as protector of the weak departs strikingly from Vivekanandas portrayal of caste elsewhere as a system of exploitation. Contradiction emerges even more sharply when Vivekananda pictures caste as a hierarchy of renunciation, with higher-placed groups cultivating morality and spirituality through material self-restraint:

The higher the caste, the greater the restrictions. The lowest caste people can eat and drink anything they like. But as men rise in the social scale, more and more restrictions come

This hierarchy of material renunciation culminates with Brahmins, the poorest of all the classes in the country, says Vivekananda, who never covet wealth. Vivekanandas sociology breaks down in his attempt to defend Vedantic religion as a source of moralizing and even socialist institutions. Caste as a hierarchy of renunciation integrates poorly with caste as a hierarchy of exploitation.

This contradiction in Vivekanandas doctrine of caste points subtler problems in his theories of social change and democracy. With such contradictory views on the nature of caste, Vivekananda cannot help but equivocate on the question of eradicating it. In one voice, he argues that caste is bondage, and Indias greatest dividing factor. Caste is a barrier to Indias progress. It narrows, restricts, separates. In another voice, he insists that, caste is a very good thing, one of the greatest social institutions ever devised. For India, caste is the plan we want to follow, because it is destined to lead Indian humanity to its goal. Though Vivekanandas views are deeply unsettled, he occasionally hints at a reconciliation. He imagines preserving caste as division of labor but destroying it as a system of exploitation. The division of labor will operate without such privileges as allow higher castes to trample on lower ones.

Eradication of exploitation does not, for Vivekananda, necessarily imply eradication of hierarchy. There will, it seems, be some castes to rule society and do its intellectual work, others to do its menial work. Though somewhat ambiguously, Vivekananda supports the notion that such divisions be based on aptitude and merit rather than birth.

Vivekananda envisions a sort of hierarchical socialism in which power differentials exist, but without exploitation. Such is his picture of the ancient caste system, prior to corruption by high-caste oppression and exploitation. He imagines a revival of that old order, such that Brahmins would once again exemplify renunciatory values and virtues, while tutoring lower groups progressively in them:

The plan in India is to make everybody a Brahmin, the Brahmin being the ideal of humanity. If you read the history of India, you will find that attempts have always been made to raise the lower classes. Many are classes that have been raised. Many more will follow till the whole will become Brahmin. That is the plan. We have only to raise them without bringing down anybody. And this has mostly to be done by the Brahmins themselves

One difficulty with this hierarchical vision is that it contradicts Vivekanandas other model of progress: mass action by the dispossessed, culminating in a Shudra regime of popular self-rule. Vivekananda the revivalist is at odds with Vivekananda the revolutionary. To be sure, Vivekananda hints that a truly egalitarian order would perhaps emerge from the system of hierarchical socialism and elite-managed change. Moreover, the two models can partially be reconciled through his notion of elite-sponsored education transmitting spiritual and material wherewithal that the downtrodden require so as to improve their own lives. The moral ascendancy of Brahmin-hood dovetails with the social ascendancy of Shudra-hood.

There is, nevertheless, a disturbing paternalistic flavor to Vivekanandas hierarchical socialism, a flavor poorly concealed by his naive faith in the liberating power of mere education. Education initiated by the elite will slowly and gently alleviate oppression. Meanwhile, there must be no direct attack upon exploitational arrangements. Vivekananda admonishes activists to take care not to set up class-strife between the poor peasants, the laboring people, and wealthy classes. No direct attack is needed because the exploitative order is historically destined to disappear through the activity of the upper classes.

Vivekananda argues that the historical role of a ruling class is to dig its own grave-pave the way to its own demise and toward eventual end of exploitation. This seems to borrow from Marxism, but there is a crucial difference between a Marxist formulation and Vivekanandas. In Marxist theory, there is a cunning to history by which a ruling class, precisely through pursuit of selfish class-bound interests, unwittingly creates conditions leading to its own demise and replacement by a successor dominant class. Vivekananda, by contrast, imagines ruling classes consciously pursuing their own demise as rulers by lending generous assistance to lower classes. Though the Marxist theory may be untrue, it is certainly more plausible than Vivekanandas naivete. The sophistication Vivekananda brings to bear when criticizing piecemeal approaches to social reform deserts him when he envisions the moral regeneration of Indias ruling classes. As Vivekananda himself notes, groups do not yield their ways of life simply because reformers have criticized them.

Read the original:
What should modern independent India be and how can it get there? | EconomyNext - EconomyNext

Related Posts

Comments are closed.